Bees and societal (in)determination
Honey bee harvesting is a social phenomenon and experiments by various authors have found that only a fraction (in some studies, 20%) of the workers actually do most of the work. But a recent controlled study reported in the journal Animal Behavior by Tenczar et al (vol. 95, pp41-48, 2014, but paywalled) found that if those 'busy-bees' are removed, others step in to fill the work gap. The gist of the evidence seems to be that among the gatherer work force (and presumably other castes as well, though that's not reported), there is a spectrum of contribution and it's condition or context-dependent. As the paper says:
These bees resembled ‘elite workers’ reported in a number of other species. However, our results also show that honeybee foraging activity level is flexibly adjusted during a bee's lifetime, suggesting that in honeybees, elitism does not involve a distinct subcaste of foragers but rather stems from an extreme of a range of individual activity levels that are continuously adjusted and may be influenced by environmental cues. . . . these results support the view that individual workers continuously adjust their activity level to ensure that the colony's nutritional needs are being adequately and efficiently met, and that the net activity of the whole foraging population is likely to be one of the factors that influences this decision.
![]() |
Honeybee; Wikimedia Commons |
This of course raises the question of how the bees perceive the needs or different roles, or if the role pattern is a spectrum of activity of each bee, then how does it know when and what to do. This would relate to the bees' brains' ability to digest quite complex information and make decisions, something very interesting to try to understand, and something we wrote about here not long ago.
Intelligence
A new paper in PNAS reports the results of a large study of the genetics of IQ. Essentially, they found three genes with very small effect and unknown functional association with cognition. Indeed, one of the genes may not even be a gene. To sort this all out, of course, they say they would need a sample of a million people. One of the authors faced with this mountain of chaff is quoted this way in the story:
Benjamin says that he and his colleagues knew from the outset that their efforts might come up empty handed. But the discovery that traits such as intelligence are influenced by many genes, each having a very small effect, should help to guide future studies and also temper expectations of what they will deliver. “We haven’t found nothing,” he says.
Nice try! But the truth is that that is just what they have found:
nothing. Or, at least, nothing new, that is, no thing. We knew very
well that this was the most likely sort of finding. We have countless
precedents, including the results of countless earlier searches for genes for intelligence (and, for that matter, similar findings for most psychological/behavioral traits). Like other traits from normal ones like stature and IQ, to
body weight and major diseases of all sorts, we find polygenic control--countless contributing genetic factors with individually minimal effect. This even though usually the heritability of the trait is substantial, meaning that variation in genes together
accounts for a non-trivial fraction of the overall variation in the trait (the
environment and other factors contribute the rest, usually around 60-70%).
But heritability is a persistently subtle and misunderstood (or ignored) measure. Even with nontrivial overall heritability, the aggregate nature of the measure means we cannot say in any given individual whether his/her IQ is based on this or that particular genes, or is some specifiable percent due to genes (that is itself difficult to make sense of when referring to an individual). And heritability is often measured after taking out, or controlling for the major real causal factors, such as age and sex. Arguing for a sample for a million, if allowed and funded, is a huge fool's errand and a corrupt way to spend money (because it's mainly to keep professors off the street of unemployment).
But heritability is a persistently subtle and misunderstood (or ignored) measure. Even with nontrivial overall heritability, the aggregate nature of the measure means we cannot say in any given individual whether his/her IQ is based on this or that particular genes, or is some specifiable percent due to genes (that is itself difficult to make sense of when referring to an individual). And heritability is often measured after taking out, or controlling for the major real causal factors, such as age and sex. Arguing for a sample for a million, if allowed and funded, is a huge fool's errand and a corrupt way to spend money (because it's mainly to keep professors off the street of unemployment).
Yet the issues in these cases are subtle, because we also
know of many different individual genes that, when seriously mutated, cause
direct, major, usually congenital damage to traits like intelligence. Yet few if any of these genes show up in these mega-mapping studies. It
is this sort of landscape of elusive complexity that we need to address, rather than
just building expensive Big Data resources that will largely be obsolete before
the DNA sequence is even analyzed, based on the daydream that we are not, knowingly, chasing rainbows.
The primary question one thinks to ask is whether 'intelligence' is a biologically meaningful trait. If not, even if it can be measured and be affected by genes, it isn't really an 'it' and one can't be surprised that no strong genetic influences are found even if the measure is stable and heritable. Asking about the genetic basis of intelligence under such circumstances is not asking a well-posed question.
The primary question one thinks to ask is whether 'intelligence' is a biologically meaningful trait. If not, even if it can be measured and be affected by genes, it isn't really an 'it' and one can't be surprised that no strong genetic influences are found even if the measure is stable and heritable. Asking about the genetic basis of intelligence under such circumstances is not asking a well-posed question.
Baby stories
The other day we posted about the recent Science issue on non-genetic influences on parenting, environmental effects on traits and how long-term and subtle they can be, and how they are not Genetic in the sense of the G-rush we are currently experiencing. The stories are many and diverse and tell the same tale.
Here the fascinating question is how the various environmental factors could influence a fetus in factor-specific manners that even relate to the factor itself (e.g., maternal diet affecting the future baby's obesity level, or the effect of the mother eating garlic or being exposed to odors on taste preference or specific odor-related behavior in the child). To answer such questions we have to know more than just about a gene or two.
So, why aren't these findings grabbing headlines?
The bee story made the front-page of the NYTimes, but mainly because of the video and not because it is a counter to the strong genomic hard-wiring ethos so often promoted by scientists these days. Likewise, the baby influences made the cover of Science, but we didn't see a Hot-News blare announcing that genetics isn't, after all, everything. And of course the IQ story didn't make that clear either, given that the author said he wanted studies of a million to find the real genetic causes of IQ. And, determinists say this isn't going to change their mind about the genetics of intelligence, because it's definitely genetic.
Will we, or when will we, see people begin to back off their claims of strong genetic determinism, and begin addressing the really hard questions concerning how complex genomes interact with complex environments to produce what we are clearly observing? In my opinion, these questions cannot be addressed from a genetic, or from an environmental, or from a simple Gene + Environment point of view.