For my final entry in this series, I would like to revisit some ideas from my earlier posts,
as they pertain to a book that I recently finished, called ‘What is Real?’
(Basic Books, 2018) by Adam Becker. The book recounts quantum theory’s
formative years during the early twentieth
century, focusing as much on the personalities that were involved in the theory’s development as on the
science itself.
Becker devotes much of the book to the 1927 Solvay
Conference, which gathered twenty-nine of the world’s leading physicists to
discuss the newly formulated
theory. Attendees at the conference were
divided into two ideologically
distinct groups. In the majority, were
Werner Heisenberg, Max Born, and others who
had adopted Danish physicist Niels Bohr’s ‘Copenhagen interpretation’.
Influenced by Heisenberg’s ‘uncertainty principle’, Bohr
claimed that subatomic entities had ‘complementary’ properties that could never
be measured at the same time. Electrons, for example, behaved like ‘particles’
or ‘waves’ depending on the
experiment. To Bohr, this implied that electrons, photons, and other subatomic
entities only had probabilities until they were
measured. ‘Reality’ simply did not exist in the quantum world. It was
therefore pointless to talk about what
was happening on the quantum
level, since quantum theory could not describe the way the world
‘is’.
On the other side of the aisle were Louis de Broglie, Erwin
Schrödinger, and Albert Einstein who
were adamant that physical
systems were ‘real’ whether we acknowledged
them or not. Led by Einstein, this group argued that although considerable
advances had been made in developing quantum theory, it was hardly complete. Rather than do away with
reality at the quantum level, Einstein et al. suggested that hidden processes, such
as de Broglie’s ‘pilot waves’,
could explain apparent contradictions such as wave–particle
duality.
In the end, Bohr’s instrumentalist
view won the day over Einstein’s realist one. Quantum
mechanics was a closed theory
that was no longer susceptible
to change. Einstein and his
supporters were largely
ignored, and Einstein himself was
painted as an out-of-touch curmudgeon who
simply would not accept the new theory. At least that is how the story has been told over the
past several decades. Becker, however,
gives a slightly different account. He argues that the Copenhagen
interpretation’s popularity had less to do with
its epistemological value than with
the cult of personality surrounding its architect, Niels Bohr.
Bohr was a
‘physicists’ physicist’ and the preeminent scientist of his time. In contrast
to Einstein (who described
himself as a ‘one-horse cart’), Bohr collaborated with other physicists throughout his career and
mentored many others at his institute in Copenhagen, where he enjoyed considerable financial support from
the Danish government. According to Becker, Bohr’s social influence, together with the convoluted and sometimes
confusing way that he
expressed himself, led many to revere him as a near mythical figure. Indeed, in
one particularly telling passage, Becker quotes Bohr’s former student John Archibald
Wheeler, who compared Bohr to
‘Confucius and Buddha, Jesus and Pericles, Erasmus and Lincoln’.
‘What is Real?’ serves as an important cautionary tale.
While we want to believe that science advances
only through its devotion to empirical fact, many ‘facts’ are decided upon not
by what they say, but by who says them. We each belong to a
‘thought collective’ with
fixed ideas that prevent us from seeing things objectively. Competing
ideologies are quickly swept
under the rug and forgotten. Indeed, in my experience, I have found that
students are rarely exposed to the histories and philosophies that have shaped their
respective disciplines. Do we
all have our own ‘Copenhagen
interpretation’, firmly enshrined in a scaffolding of tradition and
convenience? I suspect that we
do. To borrow a line from
Daniel C. Dennett’s, ‘Darwin’s
Dangerous Idea’: ‘There is no such thing as philosophy-free science; there is
only science whose
philosophical baggage is taken on board without
examination’.
1 comment:
You may enjoy some of the writings of Woese regarding the transformation of life sciences over the last 60-70 years. Life science got invaded by physicists, and the disciplined was turned into a clone of physics of pre-WWII. In the meanwhile, physics moved away from its hope of finding grand unified theories for everything. Especially, the discovery of superconductivity principles and other rules related to condensed matter physics showed that all natural phenomena could not be explained by "grand unified theories". Due to the culmination of those two intellectual efforts, today we treat living organisms as simple machines, but non-living materials as inherently complex.
Post a Comment